Fairness (Ακριβοδικια)
Aristotle on Equality as a Component of Justice
With regard to distribution of elements such as goods or services, Aristotle notes that fairness—or equity—can only be discussed or applied in situations in which both parties are themselves already equal in role or stature. In other words, distribution should be “equal among equals”—this can be thought of as a sort of “proportional equality” whose justice is discussed as follows:
“For if the people are not equal, they will not have equal things. Rather, from this arise fights and accusations, either when people who are equal have or are distributed unequal things, or when people who are unequal have or are distributed equal things.”
In the second scenario in which Aristotle discusses equity—which he refers to as being relevant in “transactions” between parties—one party has taken more than what is “fair”—or equitable—leaving the alternate party with less. Using examples that include theft and adultery, Aristotle discusses the role of the law as a corrective mechanism to right the injustice or inequality, saying:
“For it makes no difference at all whether a decent person robs a base one, or a base person a decent one, or if a decent or a base person commits adultery. Rather, the law looks only at the difference that stems from the harm done, and it treats persons as equals: if the one person acts unjustly, the other suffers injustice; and if the one did harm, the other was harmed. As a result, since the unjust in this sense is an inequality, the judge tries to restore equality … by inflicting a loss, thereby taking away the gain [of the other party].”
In this limited sense then, what is termed “corrective justice” appears blind as to initial parity between the parties involved in the transaction. For all other scenarios, it would appear that equity or fairness is assumed to be virtuous and just only to the degree that there was already parity in status or position of the parties involved.
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Book 5*
Translated from the original Greek by Robert C. Bartlett & Susan D. Collins**
“CHAPTER 3. Since the unjust person is unequal and what is unjust is unequal, it is clear that there is also a certain middle term associated with what is unequal. And this is the equal, for in whatever sort of action in which there are degrees, the more and the less, there is also the equal. If, then, the unjust is unequal, the just is equal, which is in fact what is held to be the case by everyone, even without argument. Since the equal is a middle term, the just would be a certain middle term. The equal involves at least two things. It is necessary, accordingly, for the just to be a middle term as well as equal, both in relation to something and for certain persons. In the respect in which it is a middle term, it is between certain things (these are the more and the less); in the respect in which it is equal, it involves two things; and in the respect in which it is just, it is for certain persons.
It is necessary, therefore, for the just to involve at least four terms: the persons for whom it happens to be just are two, and the things involved—the matters of concern—are two. And there will be the same equality for the persons and the things involved: as the latter (the things in the given circumstances) are related, so also are the former. For if the people are not equal, they will not have equal things. Rather, from this arise fights and accusations, either when people who are equal have or are distributed unequal things, or when people who are unequal have or are distributed equal things. Further, this is clear from what accords with merit, for all agree that what is just in distributions ought to accord with a certain merit. Nevertheless, all do not mean the same thing by merit; rather, democrats say it is freedom; oligarchs, wealth; others, good birth; aristocrats, virtue. The just, therefore, is a certain proportion. Proportion is not peculiar to abstract number alone, but belongs to number generally. For proportion is an equality of ratios, and it involves at least four terms.
… The just in this case, then, is the proportional; the unjust is what is contrary to the proportion. The unjust, therefore, is both what is more [than the proportion], on the one side, and what is less than it, on the other, which is in fact what happens when it comes to our deeds: he who acts unjustly has more of the good, and he who suffers injustice, less, and the reverse in the case of what is bad. For the lesser share of what is bad, compared with the greater share of it, falls into the definition of what is good: the lesser bad is more choiceworthy.”
“CHAPTER 4. The just in transactions is a certain equality, and the unjust, a certain inequality, yet not in accord with the proportion just indicated but in accord with an arithmetic one. For it makes no difference at all whether a decent person robs a base one, or a base person a decent one, or if a decent or a base person commits adultery. Rather, the law looks only at the difference that stems from the harm done, and it treats persons as equals: if the one person acts unjustly, the other suffers injustice; and if the one did harm, the other was harmed. As a result, since the unjust in this sense is an inequality, the judge tries to restore equality. For indeed, if one person is struck and the other strikes, or if he also kills him and the other dies, the suffering and the doing involved are divided into unequal segments. But the judge tries to restore equality by inflicting a loss, thereby taking away the gain. For the term gain is used as a way of speaking simply in such circumstances (even if in certain cases it would not be the proper name—for example, for the person who struck another), and the term loss is used for him who suffered. But, at any rate, whenever the suffering is measured, the one is called a loss, the other a gain. As a result, the equal is a middle term with respect to what is more and less, while the gain and the loss are more and less in opposite ways: more of the good and less of the bad is gain, the reverse is loss. The middle term with respect to these is, as we noted, the equal, which we say is just; as a result, the just that is corrective would be the middle term when it comes to loss and gain.”
*Nicomachean Ethics Book 5 = Eudemian Ethics Book 4
**Aristotle. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Translated, with an interpretive essay, notes, and glossary by Robert C. Bartlett and Susan D. Collins. London: University of Chicago Press, Ltd., 2011. (Available at Amazon)
Practical Application
for Ethical Leadership